Donate books to help fund our work. Learn more→

The Rudolf Steiner Archive

a project of Steiner Online Library, a public charity

Search results 121 through 130 of 235

˂ 1 ... 11 12 13 14 15 ... 24 ˃
255b. Anthroposophy and its Opponents: Old and New Opponents I 16 Nov 1919, Dornach

Rudolf Steiner
You see, the brochure I mentioned, which says in the introduction, in the preface: The present writing - originally a lecture at the course organized by the Evangelical Federation and held in Tübingen in August 1919 - endeavors to describe and assess Steiner's world of thought as clearly and objectively as possible.
And the important thing about this is that I have shown that one cannot at all place oneself in relation to the outer sense world in the way that Kant and all his imitators placed themselves in relation to this outer sense world, simply accepting it and asking: Is it possible to penetrate deeper into it or not?
For it has been attempted from the very beginning to prove that the sense world is not a reality, but that it is an illusory reality, to which must be added what man brings to it, what flashes up in man's inner being and what he then works out. All of Kant's and post-Kantian philosophy is based on the assumption that we have a finished reality before us and that we can then ask the question: Yes, can we recognize this finished reality or cannot we recognize it?
108. The Answers to Questions About the World and Life Provided by Anthroposophy: Formal Logic II 28 Oct 1908, Berlin

Rudolf Steiner
184. The Cosmic Prehistoric Ages of Mankind: The Threefoldness of Space and the Unity of Time 20 Sep 1918, Dornach
Tr. Mabel Cotterell

Rudolf Steiner
Three dimensions standing at right angles to one another, or even all that geometry has to say about space,—how frightfully abstract, how prosaic and poverty-stricken, so poverty-stricken that the whole of space—with time as well—has become for Kant subjective shadow, merely a form of conceiving sense-phenomena. This abstraction, space, of which modern man knows little more than that it has length, breadth and height, this abstraction, space, was a very different conception in the far past, of which, however, something still exists today for especially sensitive people—though indeed it is only a trace.
1. 15th September 1918
167. Things in Past and Present in the Spirit of Man: Fragments from the Jewish Haggada 23 May 1916, Berlin
Tr. E. H. Goddard

Rudolf Steiner
165. The Conceptual World and Its Relationship to Reality: Lecture Two 16 Jan 1916, Dornach

Rudolf Steiner
169. Toward Imagination: The Twelve Human Senses 20 Jun 1916, Berlin
Tr. Sabine H. Seiler

Rudolf Steiner
On theology there were only the most essential works, the Bollandist writings and a good deal of Franciscan literature, Meister Eckhart, writings on the spiritual exercises, Catherine of Genoa, the mysticism of Gorres and Mohler's symbolism. On philosophy there were more books: all of Kant's works, including the collected volumes of the Kant Society, also Deussen's Upanishads and his history of philosophy, Vaihinger's philosophy of the As if, and very many books on epistemology.
Lost the first battle of the Marne (Sept. 1914) and was relieved of his command (Nov. 1914).2. Eduard von Hartmann, 1842–1906, German philosopher.
10. Richard M. Meyer, 1860–1914, German philologist.11. Franz Ferdinand, 1863–1914, Archduke of Austria.
185. From Symptom to Reality in Modern History: Brief Reflections on the Publication of the New Edition of ‘The Philosophy of Freedom’ 30 Oct 1918, Dornach
Tr. A. H. Parker

Rudolf Steiner
With this ethical individualism the whole Kantian school, of course, was ranged against me, for the preface to my essay Truth and Science opens with the words: ‘We must go beyond Kant.’ I wanted at that time to draw the attention of my contemporaries to Goetheanism—the Goetheanism of the late nineteenth century however—through the medium of the so-called intellectuals, those who regarded themselves as the intellectual elite.
7 You can imagine the alarm of contemporaries who were gravitating towards total philistinism, when they read this sentence:T3 When Kant apostrophizes duty: ‘Duty! thou sublime and mighty name, thou that dost embrace within thyself nothing pleasing, nothing ingratiating, but dost demand submission, thou that dost establish a law ... before which all inclinations are silent even though they secretly work against it,’ then, out of the consciousness of the free spirit, man replies: ‘Freedom!
15. Rosa Luxemburg (1870–1919). Radical Socialist, worked for overthrow of existing regime. Opposed to war 1914. Author of ‘Spartakus’ letters 1916.
251. The History of the Anthroposophical Society 1913–1922: Second General Assembly of the Anthroposophical Society — Day Three 20 Jan 1914, Berlin

Rudolf Steiner
Then page 4: But reason and science rebel against the categorical imperative, the longer, the more. Kant, great though he was, was not infallible. The imperative of conscience is not categorical in and of itself, nor is it categorical in any other way than that of the sexual drive, fear, motherly love or other feelings and drives.
Recently I read from him – I am almost ashamed to say it – an “academic treatise” about what mathematics actually is as a science. He refers to Kant, and what he says about the methodological foundations of the mathematical sciences and their relationship to other sciences is the most immature, childish stuff.
Steiner has consistently refrained from speaking since the summer of 1911. I must of course remain silent here about his private comments to me; I can only reveal that they were neither warm nor cold.
254. The Occult Movement in the Nineteenth Century: Lecture II 11 Oct 1915, Dornach
Tr. Dorothy S. Osmond

Rudolf Steiner
175. Building Stones for an Understanding of the Mystery of Golgotha: Lecture IX 01 May 1917, Berlin
Tr. A. H. Parker

Rudolf Steiner
This self-awareness of reason, the consciousness of its boundaries, of the limitations of its own power when bereft of the divine afflatus, began with Kant. He recognized that reason of itself cannot achieve that which by its very nature it is constrained to will; it cannot achieve the goal it has set itself. He called a halt to reason at the very moment where it promised to be fruitful. Kant set boundaries to reason, but his disciples extended these boundaries and each went his own way. Ultimately godless reason had no other choice but to abdicate.
Max Scheler (1874–1928). Professor of Philosophy at Cologne, 1920–21. His writings have a strong theistic flavour and he was a subtle advocate of Catholicism. Note 7.

Results 121 through 130 of 235

˂ 1 ... 11 12 13 14 15 ... 24 ˃